Lap Dancing on the Constitution
George Will, June 27, 2003
Eager to improve their town’s moral tone, Los Angeles
city councilors are considering an ordinance to improve decorum at strip
clubs: no lap dances—dancers are required to remain six feet from
customers—no direct tipping, no private VIP rooms in clubs with full nudity.
Advocates of the ordinance say such goings-on lead to prostitution.
Opponents of the ordinance, including the dancers, deny
that prostitution flourishes at the clubs. And they call the ordinance an
unconstitutional abridgement of free artistic-expression. But a federal
appeals court upheld a law in Washington state requiring dancers to stay 10
feet from customers. Opponents should haul out the heavy constitutional
artillery—the privacy right.
Given the Supreme Court’s 6 to 3 ruling yesterday that
Texas’s anti-sodomy law violates the constitutional privacy right, lap
dancing—like prostitution, for that matter—looks like a fundamental
constitutional right. Consider the discontinuities in the evolution of that
right, which the court first explicitly affirmed in 1965, more than 17 decades
after the Constitution was ratified.
In 1965 the court said a Connecticut law banning the sale
and use of contraceptives violated a constitutional right of privacy. But the
court connected this right to society’s stake in an institution—marriage,
“an association that promotes a way of life.” Marriage is grounded in
nature, in the generation and rearing of children, a matter about which every
society legislates.
The privacy right is most famously associated with Roe v.
Wade, the 1973 abortion decision. But the radicalism of that decision was in
severing the privacy right from any relationship with any social institution.
Rather, the court said in 1973 that the privacy right encompasses the
individual’s right of choice. In sexual conduct, the right to choose is the
right to consensual activity.
In the 1973 severing, the court said the privacy right
involves “freedom from government domination in making the most intimate and
personal decisions.” Such as to choose to engage in sodomy. So the court
contradicted its 1973 privacy right ruling when, in 1986, it voted 5 to 4 to
affirm a Georgia law criminalizing consensual adult sodomy. And one justice in
that majority, Lewis Powell, later said he regretted his vote.
Yesterday the court held that Texas’s law “furthers
no legitimate state interest” that can justify abridging the privacy right
to consensual adult homosexual activity. The logic of the ruling, which the
court flinches from recognizing, is that no legitimate state interest is
served by any law for the promotion of a majority’s convictions about sexual
morality.
In the 1986 case, the court said it was being asked to
“announce . . . a fundamental right to engage in homosexual sodomy. This we
are quite unwilling to do.” Yesterday the court seemed to think it still had
not done so. It was mistaken.
Today laws criminalizing homosexual sodomy are rare and
rarely enforced. They should be repealed. In most states they have been, by
democratic persuasion.
But “unconstitutional” is not a synonym for
“unjust” or “unwise,” and the Constitution is not a scythe that judges
are free to wield to cut down all laws they would vote to repeal as
legislators. Legislators can adjust laws to their communities’ changing
moral sensibilities without creating, as courts do, principles, such as the
broadly sweeping privacy right, that sweep away more than communities intend
to discard.
The question is not whether states are wise to
criminalize this or that sex act outside of marriage. Rather, the question is:
Once the court has said that some such acts are constitutional rights, by what
principle are any of the myriad possible permutations of consensual adult
sexual activities denied the same standing?
Once consent—“choice”—supplants marriage as the
important interest served by cloaking sexual activities as constitutional
rights, by what principle is any consensual adult sexual conduct not a
protected right? Bigamy? Polygamy? Prostitution? Incest? Even—if we assume
animals can consent, or that their consent does not matter—bestiality?
By what has been called “semantic infiltration,”
seemingly bland language stealthily permeates discourse with ideology. So it
is with the now commonplace locution “sexual preferences.”
If preferences are all that they are, if none are
grounded in nature rather than mere conventions or appetites, then by what
principle are they not all equal? And given that in a 1992 abortion ruling the
privacy right was explained as “the right to physical autonomy,” the
question is not just whether there is a fundamental right to engage in sodomy.
Why not the right to physical autonomy in using heroin?
Lap dancing as a fundamental right? That is, after
yesterday, not a close constitutional call.
Will Has Strange Take on Sexual Freedom, Privacy
Seattle
Post-Intelligencer, July 7, 2003
101 Elliot Avenue W, Seattle, WA 98119
Fax: 206-448-8184
Email: editpage@seattle-pi.com
George Will established himself as a legitimate baseball
authority with his book “Men at Work: The Craft of Baseball” (1990). While
his analysis of the intricacies of baseball is superb, his take on sexual
freedom and privacy is woeful.
In his June 29 column, Will asks, given the Supreme Court
decision on the Texas sodomy law, “by what principle is any consensual adult
sexual conduct not a protected right? Bigamy? Polygamy? Prostitution?
Incest?” Will’s logic is terrible. He forgets that prostitution involves
the selling, and thus the exploitation, of one person’s body in a sexual
liaison and that incest is most often the brutal sexual exploitation of
children. Child incest is never mutually consensual and prostitution seldom
is, involving as it usually does the economic and sexual exploitation of poor
women. Bigamy and polygamy, while perhaps unacceptable to most adults, do
involve consenting adults, and neither of these sexual arrangements involves
exploitation of one adult by another or the destruction of a child’s
emotional and sexual integrity.
Stick to baseball, George. You’re much better at games
than you are at politics.
—Michael Shurgot, Seattle
Will Thinks Consensual Sex Should Be Illegal
What dictionary is George Will using? Since when is
marriage, much less bigamy or polygamy, a sex act? By his logic, any sex act
by consenting adults who are not married to each other should or would be
illegal. I realize that there is a cadre of people in this country who believe
that is the case. Perhaps Will is one of them but is not bold enough to say
so.
Will and others (right or left) lose credibility when
they resort to dramatic overstatement or do not directly state their position,
assuming that readers are too dimwitted to know the difference.
—Ruth Frickle, Seattle
[Home] [Editorials] [Lawrence
v. Texas]